Executive Summary
Determining whether investment results are due to luck or skill is no small task for even skilled analysts evaluating an active investment manager; given the amount of randomness inherent in markets, it can be very difficult to determine which is which. Fortunately, the field of inferential statistics exists specifically to analyze such situations and help to distinguish the signal from the noise, and determine when results are likely randomness and luck versus when there is at least a high probability that skill or some other factor is at play.
When inferential statistics is applied to evaluating active management, the results are questionable at best - a small subset of managers are clearly inferior, and for virtually all the rest, there are simply no clear indicators of skill at all; even when some modest level of outperformance occurs, the results are rarely ever statistically significant. Of course, just because an actively managed fund has outperformance that is not statistically significant doesn't mean the manager isn't actually generating real outperformance and adding value. It's just that the outperformance isn't large enough relative to overall market volatility to clearly show whether the results are due to luck or skill.
Unfortunately, though, the caveat is that given just how incredibly volatile markets really are, searching for "statistically significant" outperformance may actually be a lousy approach for evaluating managers; even if a manager really does outperform for an extended period of time, the available tests simply are not capable of distinguishing skill from market noise given the tenure of even long-standing managers. In fact, when tested to determine the effectiveness of the approach in the first place, the reality is that even if a manager is adding several hundred basis points of outperformance, annually, for more than a decade, there is still a more-than-90% likelihood that inferential statistics will FAIL to identify the signal that really is there.
In other words, if the goal is actually to determine which active managers really do add value, searching for statistically significant outperformance is an approach with an overwhelming likelihood to fail, even in situations where it should be succeeding! Which means in the end, failing to find statistically significant outperformance amongst active managers may actually be less a failure of active management itself, and more a problem with using an approach that was unlikely to successfully identify good managers in the first place!
Understanding Inferential Statistics
The basic principle of inferential statistics is fairly straightforward - to try to draw conclusions from data that is muddled by randomness. Viewed another way, its goal is to find signals amidst noise.
Of course, sometimes there is a lot of noise, so the process of inferential statistics is fairly conservative in its approach, to avoid drawing inappropriate conclusions. If the difference between A and B is not significant - not statistically significant - it's assumed to just be a result of noise and not a signal. In other words, inferential statistics tries to minimize the risk that we make a mistake - called a Type I error - of saying that A and B are different when in fact they're not.
On the other hand, given that we only draw a conclusion about whether A and B are different in scenarios where the magnitude of the difference - the signal - is larger than the magnitude of the randomness - the noise - it can be very difficult to draw much of a conclusion about anything. Fortunately, as the number of measurements increases, the randomness tends to cancel itself out; as a result, larger sample sizes (assuming they're sampled appropriately) tend to have less randomness, which makes it easier to differentiate the signal from the noise.
For instance, if I'm trying to determine whether the average height of men is taller than the average height of women in my local neighborhood, it's not so clear if I just measure one or two people. The fact that the first two men to be measured happen to average 5' 5" and the two women average 5' 3" doesn't mean we can draw a conclusion that men are taller than women where I live. After measuring only four people, it's possible the conclusion would be wrong just due to random chance (maybe I bumped into some especially tall or short neighbors). Yes, according to the sample the men are 2 inches taller than women on average, but given that human beings - both male and female - can vary from under 5 feet to over 7 feet, a 2 inch difference from measuring only four people just isn't enough to affirm that the difference is statistically significant. Or viewed another way, if I determined after just a few people that the height of men in my neighborhood is 5' 5" plus-or-minus 6 inches, and the height of the women is 5' 3" plus-or-minus 6 inches, then clearly the 2-inch difference between them isn't all that significant given the +/- 6 inch bands of uncertainty.
On the other hand, if we keep growing our sample by measuring more people, on average our estimates should move towards the true heights for all men and women in my area, and the variability should decline, as a few randomly tall or short people both tend to cancel each other out, and become less of an impact on the overall average as the number of people grows. For instance, after several dozen measurements, we might find that the average height of men in my area is 5' 8" and that women are 5' 4", and that based on randomness alone we're 95% certain those estimates are accurate within +/- 3.5 inches. Notably, this means we have now crossed the threshold of statistical significance; when the difference between the groups is 4 inches, and there's a less-than-5% chance that a difference larger than 3.5 inches could be due to randomness alone, we draw the conclusion that the men in the area are in fact taller than women because the odds the observed 4-inch difference is due to chance alone is small.
Technically, we still haven't proven it, because we haven't measured everyone in fact, our measurements haven't even precisely predicted the actual height of men and women nationwide (which is actually 5' 9.5" vs 5' 4" respectively in the US). Nonetheless, when we reach the point where the differences are so large that there's a less-than-5% chance it's due to randomness alone, we assume we've got a signal. Technically, that less-than-5% chance also represents our probability of a Type I error, also known as (statistical) alpha - i.e., that the men around here really aren't taller than women, and that our sampled difference really is just random noise.
Notably, though, back when my sample of four people wasn't large enough to determine whether the 2-inch difference was noise or just a signal, it would be wrong to conclude that "the men are not taller than women here" just because we didn't have a statistically significant difference. Failing to have a large enough sample to separate noise from signal doesn't mean there is no signal, just that we don't have enough data to draw a conclusion that there is a signal. This is important, because in some situations we are limited to the number of measurements we can make; for instance, if I only had the time to measure half a dozen people total, there is a significant risk that, even though the men here really are taller than women, the differences between our small sample of men and women wouldn't be large enough to affirm statistical significance. This scenario - where there really is a signal, but we fail to successfully detect it amidst the noise - is called a Type II error, and is especially common when we don't have a large enough sample to minimize the noise (and accordingly, the noisier the data, the larger the necessary sample).
Confidence Intervals, Type I and Type II Errors, And Statistical Power
Ultimately, we try to affirm that we're not making a Type I error by determining not just the average of our samples and whether one is bigger on average than the other, but the (typically 95%) confidence intervals around those averages, and we don't draw a conclusion that group A is different than group B until the magnitude of the difference between them is greater than what we might expect from merely randomness within our confidence interval alone. Of course, sometimes the actual difference between the groups - called the effect size - isn't all that large to begin with, so it may require an extremely big sample to hone the randomness down to the point where the confidence interval is so small, we're finally able to distinguish a signal from the noise. For instance, if the truth was that men really were taller than women in my neighborhood, but the average difference was actually only half an inch, I'd need to measure a lot of people before I could safely draw a conclusion about such a small difference.
On the other hand, sometimes this itself can actually be a problem. If the truth is that the effect size really is fairly small, but the groups have a lot of variability, and we're limited in how big of a sample size we can gather in the first place, there's an increasingly high likelihood that we will fail to find a signal in the noise and make a Type II error. Not because there isn't a signal, but simply because it was very difficult to detect the signal due to the combination of small effect size, high variability, and limited sample. In fact, inferential statistics uses a measure called "statistical power" (also known as statistical beta) to calculate, given a certain anticipated effect size, an estimate of variability, and the available sample size, the likelihood that the researcher will make a Type II error, failing to detect the actual signal that was really there.
Notably, these measures all impact each other as well. The wider we draw the confidence intervals, the more we reduce the risk of a Type I error (by making it harder and harder to draw a conclusion about a signal by assuming there is a larger amount of noise), but the more we reduce the statistical power and increase the risk of making a Type II error (by making it so hard to distinguish real signals in the noise that we mistakenly fail to detect them when they're really there).
In general, statisticians err in the direction of not identifying signals that turn out to be noise - in other words, we set the risk of a Type I error at a fairly low level, even at the "cost" of reducing statistical power - but it's important to realize that in some circumstances, statistical power may turn out to be very low indeed.
Inferential Statistics Applied To Active Investment Management
So what does all of this have to do with active management? The all-too-common approach for evaluating whether there is value in active management overall, or an actively managed fund in particular, is to measure the results of the fund against the results of the index, to see whether the results are "statistically significant" - in other words, given the underlying randomness inherent in the index itself, and the randomness that would occur from an active manager merely due to chance, is the difference between the two large enough that we can distinguish a signal from noise?
The problem, unfortunately, is that measuring the results of investment performance is a classic scenario where the variability is high (the standard deviation of equities is typically estimated around 20% or a bit more based on annual returns), and the effect sizes are likely modest at best. After all, even if the fund manager can outperform, an amazing manager still might "only" outperform by a few percent per year on average, which is dwarfed by the 20% annual volatility of equities. Of course, the measurement of random volatility alone will decline over time (technically by the square root of the number of years), but that too is constrained - until a manager has a longer track record, there simply aren't all that many years available to measure in the first place. The net result - even if there is a signal and the active manager is creating outperformance, at a level that can still accrue a material amount of long-term wealth, it can be remarkably difficult to measure it using inferential statistics. Instead, the overwhelming likelihood is that a Type II error will be made, failing to identify the signal even when there is one.
How bad is the risk? Let's say we have an equity manager who is actually capable of outperforming his benchmark by 100 basis points per year (after netting all appropriate fees). While this is a fairly modest level of investment outperformance, it's nonetheless quite material over a long period of time; with stocks averaging about 10% annualized over the long run, a $10,000 indexed portfolio would grow to $174,494 after 30 years, but the manager with an 11% annualized return would grow to $228,923, a whopping 31.2% increase in wealth. In a lower return environment - for instance, if stocks only provide a return of 8% going forward - the 1% outperformance has a slightly greater impact on a lower base, resulting in future wealth of $100,627 in the index returning 8% and $132,677 from the fund manager earning 9% (a 31.9% difference in wealth).
Yet placed against a backdrop of equities with 20% volatility, it turns out to be remarkably difficult to affirm that the results are an actual signal. Using this statistical power calculator to compare the manager (fund being evaluated) versus the population (the benchmark index) to measure a continuum of potential results, we find that after 5 years of a manager averaging 11% while the index averages 10% with a 20% standard deviation, the statistical power is a whopping... 3.2%. In other words, assuming the manager really is capable of outperforming by 1% per year, there's only a 3.2% chance that our approach will correctly identify this, and a 96.8% chance that we'll fail to realize the manager as successful using inferential statistics. What happens if we wait 10 years? Not much better... the statistical power only rises to 3.6%. After 30 years? 4.6%.
Yup, that's right; using inferential statistics, even a manager who outperforms by 1% per year for an entire 30-years (what could be his/her whole career at that point!) still has a 95.4% chance of being "indistinguishable from noise" by the end. If the manager outperforms by 2.5% per year - which will double the investor's final wealth after 30 years of compounding - the statistical power is still only 10.1%. To put that in real dollar terms, that means if Investor A finishes with $1,000,000, and Investor B finishes with $2,000,000 because his investment manager is brilliant for 30 years, inferential statistics would still conclude there's an 89.9% chance that this was just random luck. After 30 years. If you were merely giving the manager a "typical" 3-5 years to establish a track record, the statistical power falls back below 5%, even assuming a whopping 2.5%/year outperformance effect size.
So what's the bottom line to all of this? Simply put, assessing whether a manager is "good" or "successful" or not by using inferential statistics to determine whether the outperformance is likely due to skill or indistinguishable from chance is a virtually useless way to approach the problem of manager assessment. Over what most investors would consider a "generous" time horizon, like 3-5 years of building a track record, the methodology has a whopping 95%+ probability of failing to identify a real manager who actually creates real enhancements to return. Even over multi-decade time periods, there's still a 90% failure rate for the approach to accurately detect material outperformance. That's simply the reality of trying to measure relatively "modest" differences of a few percentage points a year of outperformance against a backdrop of 20% standard deviations.
Fortunately, the volatility is less severe for some other asset classes - which improves the statistical power - but unfortunately less volatile asset classes also tend to have smaller effect sizes (less outperformance potential in the first place), which means the methodology is equally problematic there, too. Of course, in some cases investment managers are so bad that their results statistically significant - to the downside - and despite the problems of inferential statistics, those are clearly managers to avoid (just as you have to be really good to be identified as such by inferential statistics, if the results are statistically significant in the other direction, the manager must have been really bad!).
But for the overwhelming majority of funds - where technically, the results were not statistically significantly bad, but merely failed to be significantly significant in the positive direction - skill is not disproven but simply not able to be distinguished from luck. And given what constitutes "good" outperformance relative to the volatility of equities, distinguishing luck from skill using this kind of approach is actually almost impossible. Which means the reality is that failing to distinguish luck from skill when evaluating a manager may be less a problem of the manager, and more a problem of the tool being used to do the measurement in the first place. Because in the end, trying to evaluate active management with tests of statistical significance is in fact significantly likely to be wrong, even when the manager actually makes calls that are right. Which means in turn, if you want to evaluate the prospective value of an investment manager, it's perhaps time to focus on more qualitative methodologies (evaluating incentives, knowledge, experience, governance, process, etc.), because inferential statistics just isn't capable of doing the job.
Dick Purcell says
Michael, if there were some scoreboard in the sky rating blog messages in importance for investor protection, this one would rank near the very top. Maybe #1.
If it were applied to remove all offending numbers in recommendations of funds, investment managers, and stocks, think of the number of numbers that would disappear.
But it isn’t only investors that are imperiled by promotion of statistically meaningless numbers. The same thing imperils the reputation of the FP profession and the movement for the Fiduciary Standard.
Consider Fiduciary360. That entity is out there prominently campaigning for the U. S. Fiduciary Standard, and leading establishment of a worldwide Fiduciary Standard.
BUT — at the same time it’s providing “investment fiduciary” training and certification to advisors who use its oceans of rating scores for thousands of actively managed funds and other investments – rating scores so lacking in statistical significance they may as well have been prepared by the Onion. One example of the rigor applied is their recommendation that the investment manager of a fund have been on the job for TWO (2) years!
Is it fiduciary for advisors to justify their fees by splashing around in this ocean of statistical insignificance?
Another major feature of their training is that the “fiduciary” should choose an investment for a client so that the investment’s “expected return” would meet the client’s needs. That’s sufficient so that for most long-term plans, it promises a probability of failure of only 60% to 70%.
Fiduciary360 certainly has some excellent features and has developed valuable networks of fiduciary advocacy here and internationally. But with such widespread public resentment of anything “financial,” its misuse of investment numbers is a danger to the reputation of the FP profession and Fiduciary Standard campaign.
Can anything be done to remove the worst of this kind of thing from fiduciary training, rules, and tools? It’s why I think we need a Fiduciary EDUCATION Standard.
Dick Purcell
Russell Campbell says
Although you’ve addressed this topic from a slightly different angle, your note could be a companion piece/rebuttal to my blog posting on the CFA Institute web site last week under “Inside Investing”. My point was that it is worth trying to identify good managers, and your examples confirm that it is worthwhile trying. Even if there is only a 10% chance that you can double your return, it seems to me that is worth trying for. You further demonstrate that we can identify really poor managers using statistical measures – which is very helpful. Cut off the bottom performers in the manager universe and your odds of being above average go up! – The median manager in the truncated universe will have a return that is higher than the median in the full universe. You then argue that statistical analysis starts to breakdown, and we need to look to qualitative support for manager selection. Fortunately there has been a lot of work published in the FAJ and elsewhere that suggests some of the qualitative drivers associated with managers that outperform. These references were mentioned in another blog posting of mine on the same CFA site. Thanks for your comments.
Dick Purcell says
Russell –
It’s always a pleasure to see optimism.
But it appears to me that in your comment, and in your CFA blog, you’ve overlooked risk.
In your blog you concede that active management generally underperforms passive. For most folks, whose retirement income may be at risk, that’s compelling — especially in light of Michael’s conclusion that statistics are not effective in pinpointing the few active winners.
And I bet the underperformance you report in your CFA blog fails to consider that going with active is more risky. It’s less diversified. It’s betting on particular individuals. Sharpe’s Investment text calls this increased risk “active risk.”
To incorporate this increased risk in the assessment, we’d have to, in effect, on the frontier graph locate an active manager to right of his asset class, where the benchmark return rate he has to beat is higher.
I don’t know of any research on how far to right of the asset class, to reflect the extra risk of active, or how much that raises the benchmark the active manager has to beat. Do either of you know of any such research, Michael or Russell?
Including that extra “active risk” in the assessment may give us more statistically meaningful information. But if so, it will not be what advocates of active management want to see. It will all be on the negative underperformance side.
Dick Purcell
Steve Smith says
But unlike the relative heights of men and women (or just men, for that matter), we know that investment outerperformance is, mathematically, a zero sum game. If I’m the GM of a basketball team looking for a center, it’s comforting to know that in order to find a 7 footer, his existence is not because of the existence of a 4 foot man, who, by virtue of growing a few inches the next year, will make it harder for me to find a savior for my team.
Michael Kitces says
Steve,
By definition of the average, measuring how far above- or below-average someone’s height is also becomes a zero-sum game. If the sum of above-average heights is greater than the sum of below-average heights, the average moves until it’s zero sum. Mathematically that’s essentially how an average is calculated in the first place.
in other words, the distribution of results around an average will always be zero sum. That doesn’t mean it’s useless to seek out people who are above-average.
– Michael
Joe Alfonso says
My take on all this is the following:
1. Out performance is rare especially over investment horizons of 20+ years (5 years is a crap shoot, not an investment horizon)
2. Out performance is only evident after the fact
3. The incidence of out performance is no more than what you would expect by chance
4. It it therefore not clear if luck or skill is the reason for observed out performance
5. Markets are highly efficient which argues against the skill argument
6. Given all the unknowns, isn’t the most prudent course to take one of seeking market returns as efficiently as possible? There IS a proven way to achieve this, namely passive investing.
7. There are statistically validated sources of excess return versus the market (small cap, value). Targeting these within a passive approach is justified; betting on any one active manager is not.
If you disagree with me, tell me then specifically what the specific elements of investing skill are and how these can be observed in advance to identify outperforming managers ex ante, when it matters.
PavelD says
There is an important distinction between the question you addressed and the one argued by EMH proponents and detractors.
Here is what I think you addressed: How likely are we to find significant differences in performance between an individual manager and his/her benchmark? Are parametric statistical methods appropriate for measuring the performance of an individual manager?
Here is the question that was not addressed: Can inferential statistics provide a valid answer about the relative roles of skill vs. luck across many investment managers? If variance in returns across many years, across many managers, is in part driven by systematic difference in skill, how likely are we to detect these differences, again using parametric inferential statistics?
We have far more statistical power to answer questions about skill vs. luck when we compare many managers to one another than when comparing a single manager to a single benchmark. Answers to the second set of questions do not tell us how confident we should be that the particular manager we picked has skill (on the basis of historical performance). But they do tell us something about the expected returns to effort in search of a skilled manager.
By the way, you article was very clear that it addresses the first set. I just thought it would be useful to point out the second set of questions, since many folks (mostly academics?) are interested in them as well.
Michael Harris says
There are certain randomization tests you can do to determine if there is skill or luck but nothing can be proven, only falsified, unfortunately. Thus, the whole issue is a strawman. A few examples: http://www.priceactionlab.com/Blog/2015/11/random-trading/